< Return to Video

Game Theory Part 1: The Prisoners' Dilemma

  • 0:06 - 0:08
    >> Let's talk a little
    bit about game theory.
  • 0:08 - 0:11
    Some times in economics
    people want to be able
  • 0:11 - 0:13
    to describe situations
  • 0:13 - 0:15
    that involve what we call
    strategic interaction.
  • 0:16 - 0:18
    Strategic interaction just means
  • 0:18 - 0:22
    that now not only does your pay
    off, your profit, your utility,
  • 0:22 - 0:26
    how ever you want to think about
    it depend on your own choices
  • 0:26 - 0:29
    but it also depends on the
    choices of other people
  • 0:29 - 0:33
    in your market, in your
    industry and so on and so forth.
  • 0:34 - 0:37
    Typical examples of strategic
    interaction usually involves
  • 0:37 - 0:39
    decision among firms
    regarding whether
  • 0:39 - 0:42
    to cooperate or to compete.
  • 0:43 - 0:44
    We're going to go
    over and example
  • 0:44 - 0:46
    that has a slightly
    different context known
  • 0:46 - 0:50
    as the prisoner's dilemma where
    people are deciding whether
  • 0:50 - 0:52
    or not to confess to
    a particular crime.
  • 0:52 - 0:56
    The set up of the prisoner's
    dilemma is a tad bit contrived
  • 0:57 - 0:58
    but it goes as follows.
  • 0:58 - 1:01
    Imagine a situation in
    which two people are brought
  • 1:02 - 1:03
    in for supposedly
    committing a crime.
  • 1:04 - 1:06
    Now these two people are
    held in separate cells
  • 1:06 - 1:09
    so they can't talk to
    each other and even
  • 1:09 - 1:11
    if they could they couldn't
    somehow contract on whether
  • 1:11 - 1:13
    or not they were going
    to confess to the crime.
  • 1:14 - 1:16
    The people are then
    brought in individually
  • 1:17 - 1:19
    and asked do you confess
    or do you not confess?
  • 1:21 - 1:24
    We can represent the pay off's
    to that sort of situation
  • 1:24 - 1:26
    in a table as follows.
  • 1:26 - 1:31
    You'll notice here that we
    have player 1 and player 2.
  • 1:31 - 1:34
    I made things nicely color coded
  • 1:34 - 1:38
    such that we have player 1's
    pay off's in terms of utility
  • 1:39 - 1:43
    in blue to match play 1 and
    player 2's pay off's in terms
  • 1:43 - 1:46
    of utility in green here.
  • 1:47 - 1:51
    So you'll notice that if neither
    player confesses they just sit
  • 1:51 - 1:55
    there and hold tight, they
    each get a pay off of 10.
  • 1:56 - 2:00
    If the first guy keeps quiet
    and the second guy rats him
  • 2:00 - 2:05
    out the second guy gets 15 while
    the first player gets nothing.
  • 2:07 - 2:11
    The opposite happens here
    if the first player rats
  • 2:11 - 2:14
    out the second one, now
    the first player gets 15
  • 2:14 - 2:16
    and the second player
    gets nothing.
  • 2:17 - 2:20
    And if they both try to rat
    each other out, they both end
  • 2:20 - 2:24
    up with 5 meaning they're better
    off than if they just sat here
  • 2:24 - 2:27
    and had the other guy
    rat him out but not quite
  • 2:27 - 2:31
    as well off collectively
    as if they both kept quiet.
  • 2:32 - 2:38
    The question then becomes given
    this structure what's going
  • 2:38 - 2:39
    to happen.
  • 2:39 - 2:41
    In reality both players are
    making the decision of whether
  • 2:41 - 2:45
    or not to confess at the same
    time but let's just pretend
  • 2:45 - 2:47
    that they can guess or somehow
    know what the other person is
  • 2:47 - 2:50
    going to do and we can ask a
    number of hypothetical questions
  • 2:51 - 2:54
    as to what the best response
    is for these players would be.
  • 2:54 - 2:57
    So let's take the
    first case here,
  • 2:58 - 3:02
    say if player 1 confesses
    what should player 2 do?
  • 3:02 - 3:05
    In other words what's
    player 2's best response?
  • 3:06 - 3:08
    Well, we can go over here,
  • 3:08 - 3:12
    we say if player 1
    confesses we're somewhere
  • 3:12 - 3:18
    in the bottom here and player 2
    can either get zero by holding
  • 3:18 - 3:22
    out and being quiet or he
    can get 5 by confessing also.
  • 3:24 - 3:29
    Five is strictly better than
    zero so if player 1 confesses,
  • 3:29 - 3:37
    player 2 also wants to confess.
  • 3:37 - 3:39
    Now what about if
    player 1 doesn't confess,
  • 3:40 - 3:45
    well if player 1 doesn't
    confess we're up here
  • 3:45 - 3:48
    so player 2 again has two
    options, he can get 10
  • 3:48 - 3:54
    by keeping quiet or he can get
    15 by ratting out his buddy.
  • 3:55 - 3:59
    So 15 is better than 10 so
    if player 1 doesn't confess,
  • 4:01 - 4:09
    player 2 still should confess.
  • 4:09 - 4:14
    Notice here that's interesting
    that player 2 his best option is
  • 4:14 - 4:18
    to confess regardless
    of what player one does
  • 4:18 - 4:21
    or alternatively put
    player 2's best option is
  • 4:21 - 4:25
    to confess regardless of what he
    thinks player 1 is going to do.
  • 4:26 - 4:30
    This type of situation is
    called a dominant strategy
  • 4:31 - 4:33
    in that confess is
    a dominant strategy
  • 4:33 - 4:36
    for player 2 meaning it's
    always the best regardless
  • 4:36 - 4:37
    of what the other guy does.
  • 4:38 - 4:41
    Think about this the other way
    around, say we make some guesses
  • 4:41 - 4:44
    as to what player 2 is going
    to do and then when we say
  • 4:44 - 4:47
    in each case what's player 1's
    best response in that situation.
  • 4:49 - 4:51
    So if player 2 confesses,
  • 4:52 - 4:55
    what's the best thing
    for player 1 to do?
  • 4:55 - 4:58
    Say if player 2 confesses
    we're over here
  • 4:58 - 5:03
    on the right somewhere we
    say player 1 can either get 5
  • 5:03 - 5:08
    by confessing or 0 for being
    quiet this problem is looking
  • 5:08 - 5:11
    strangely familiar, say
    well 5 is better than 0
  • 5:11 - 5:17
    so player 1 is going
    to want to confess.
  • 5:19 - 5:22
    Now if player 2 doesn't
    confess what should player 1 do?
  • 5:24 - 5:27
    So if player 2 doesn't
    confess, we're over here
  • 5:27 - 5:31
    on the left somewhere and
    player 1 can either get 10
  • 5:31 - 5:34
    by being quiet or 15 by
    ratting out his buddy,
  • 5:35 - 5:45
    well 15 is greater than 10 so
    he's going to want to confess.
  • 5:45 - 5:47
    Notice here that
    because we confessed
  • 5:47 - 5:52
    in both cases confessing
    is also a dominant strategy
  • 5:52 - 5:54
    for player 1.
  • 5:55 - 5:59
    So here I've circled player
    2's best responses in green
  • 5:59 - 6:03
    and I've circled player
    1's best responses in blue
  • 6:04 - 6:07
    and you'll notice there's one
    place here where they over lap
  • 6:08 - 6:12
    to say that in this situation
    where both parties confess both
  • 6:12 - 6:15
    of them are responding
    as best they can
  • 6:16 - 6:19
    to what they think the other
    person is going to be doing.
  • 6:20 - 6:23
    We say that this situation
    here is what's called a Nash
  • 6:23 - 6:28
    equilibrium; more formally put a
    Nash equilibrium is a situation
  • 6:28 - 6:31
    where each player's
    action is the best response
  • 6:32 - 6:35
    to the other player's actions.
  • 6:35 - 6:38
    In a situation where the players
    are all moving simultaneously
  • 6:39 - 6:42
    this basically means that
    each player is reacting best
  • 6:42 - 6:44
    to what they think the
    other person is going to do
  • 6:45 - 6:46
    and they're actually
    right in their guess
  • 6:46 - 6:48
    of what the other
    person is going to do.
  • 6:56 - 7:02
    [ Pause ]
  • 7:02 - 7:07
    Notice here that the equilibrium
    outcome actually...it doesn't
  • 7:07 - 7:10
    look as good as it could
    because here we're saying
  • 7:10 - 7:13
    that any equilibrium when
    people are acting according
  • 7:13 - 7:16
    to their own best interest each
    of them ends up with a payout
  • 7:16 - 7:19
    of 5 where as if they only
    cooperated they would each get a
  • 7:19 - 7:22
    payout of 10.
  • 7:22 - 7:27
    We can say here that there can
    be a perato improvement going
  • 7:27 - 7:31
    from both parties confessing
    to both parties staying quiet
  • 7:31 - 7:34
    in that both parties
    would be made better off
  • 7:34 - 7:36
    and nobody would
    be made worse off.
  • 7:38 - 7:40
    Unfortunately, due to
    the competitive nature
  • 7:40 - 7:43
    of the this game that's
    not what's going to result
  • 7:43 - 7:46
    because it's really hard when
    there's no contracting involved
  • 7:47 - 7:51
    to guarantee regardless of
    what the other party says then
  • 7:51 - 7:53
    when it comes down to it
    they're actually going
  • 7:53 - 7:54
    to cooperate given that it's
  • 7:54 - 7:57
    in their interest
    individually to not cooperate.
  • 7:58 - 8:00
    So one question that
    economists like to think
  • 8:00 - 8:04
    about is then how can
    cooperation be sustained
  • 8:04 - 8:05
    in the real world?
  • 8:06 - 8:07
    Well, one thing that's
    important to remember here is
  • 8:07 - 8:12
    that in the real world this
    game isn't played just once,
  • 8:12 - 8:13
    when you have firms interacting
  • 8:13 - 8:17
    with each other people making
    these decisions often times they
  • 8:17 - 8:20
    have the chance to make the
    decisions over and over and over
  • 8:20 - 8:25
    so when you have what's called
    a repeated game you might have a
  • 8:25 - 8:27
    situation where people
    start testing out the waters
  • 8:27 - 8:30
    to say well maybe if I
    cooperate the other guy's going
  • 8:30 - 8:33
    to cooperate and then
    we can keep this going
  • 8:34 - 8:39
    because to cooperate here and
    hope for the best outweighs,
  • 8:39 - 8:41
    you know there's this
    threat of well if you try
  • 8:41 - 8:44
    to screw me one time we're
    reverting back here actually
  • 8:44 - 8:48
    gives in the long term an
    incentive to cooperate.
  • 8:49 - 8:52
    So like I said it seems a little
    bit artificial to be talking
  • 8:52 - 8:55
    about this context of
    prisoners being interrogated
  • 8:56 - 9:01
    because really we're
    talking about economics.
  • 9:02 - 9:08
    But it's very easy to see how
    this situation could be relevant
  • 9:08 - 9:11
    in an economic context by just
    replacing the intuition behind
  • 9:11 - 9:11
    some of the choices.
  • 9:11 - 9:14
    So what I did here is
    set up the identical game
  • 9:14 - 9:22
    and have this model as
    still player 1 and player 2
  • 9:22 - 9:26
    but now they have the
    choice of whether or not
  • 9:26 - 9:27
    to cooperate or to compete.
  • 9:27 - 9:32
    And you can see here they'd both
    do better off by cooperating
  • 9:32 - 9:35
    but they also all have the
    private incentive to compete.
  • 9:35 - 9:38
    And you can notice here
  • 9:38 - 9:41
    that this situation is
    actually pretty realistic
  • 9:43 - 9:48
    because at least in the United
    States firms are not allowed
  • 9:48 - 9:49
    to contract on whether or not
    they're going to cooperate,
  • 9:49 - 9:50
    that's called collusion,
    it's illegal.
  • 9:50 - 9:51
    So they really are
    simultaneously making
  • 9:51 - 9:52
    independent choices as
    to how much to cooperate
  • 9:52 - 9:53
    with their ''competitors''.
Title:
Game Theory Part 1: The Prisoners' Dilemma
Description:

This video introduces game theory and goes through an example of the prisoners' dilemma. It discusses the concept of Nash equilibrium and introduces the idea of a repeated game.

For more information and a complete set of microeconomics videos, see
http://www.economistsdoitwithmodels.com/microeconomics-101

by Economists Do It With Models

more » « less
Video Language:
English
Duration:
09:55

English subtitles

Revisions